Zetzel, 'Creative Selectivity in Apollonius' "Argonautica"', Bryn Mawr Classical Review 9503
URL = http://hegel.lib.ncsu.edu/stacks/serials/bmcr/bmcr-9503-zetzel-creative
@@@@95.3.11, Two studies of Apollonius
Steven Jackson, Creative Selectivity in Apollonius'
"Argonautica". Amsterdam: Hakkert, 1993. Pp. xii + 82. ISBN
90256-1066-8.
(and)
Mary Margolies DeForest, Apollonius' "Argonautica": A
Callimachean Epic. Mnemosyne, Supplement 142. Leiden: Brill,
1994. Pp. x + 160. ISBN 90-04-10017-2.
Reviewed by James E.G. Zetzel -- Columbia University
The interpretation of the Argonautica has developed
rapidly in the past generation, and the complexity and brilliance
of the poem has become ever clearer. In the context of recent
scholarship, Jackson's brief monograph, consisting of studies of
Apollonius' sources and his modifications of them in five
episodes, is something of a throwback to earlier concerns, while
DeForest's study is an attempt to interpret the entire poem as a
metafiction concerned with the struggle between competing types
of literary theory in Alexandria. Jackson's goals are modest, and
his analyses are sometimes useful; DeForest's book is far more
ambitious in its approaches, but while its goals are admirable,
and while it contains some intriguing interpretations, it is far
less successful in achieving the goals it sets for itself.
Consider, for instance, the two treatments of the Phineus
episode in book 2, one of the most important scenes in the first
half of the Argonautica. Jackson analyzes the sources,
concluding that Apollonius has chosen a Hesiodic framework for
the myth of Phineus (as opposed to the grim story of the blinding
of Phineus' children in Sophocles), but that in fact no earlier
version of the tale of the Argonauts included a meeting between
Jason and Phineus. He argues that the Phineus episode as a whole
is (14) "a lesson to Jason in the avoidance of hybris and
the necessity of themis" and that the encounter is part of
Jason's education in the Argonautica. Jackson sees the
Argonautica as focussed on Jason's "character, nature, and
thoughts" in various situations, and describes his education, his
departure from and return (in the story of Euphemus in Book 4) to
themis, and his pragmatic devotion to ananke
throughout the poem. Jackson's Argonautica is, by and
large, a moral tale. For DeForest, on the other hand, Phineus is
a representative of the Callimachean narrator of the
Argonautica, twisting the tale away from the Homeric and
towards the Callimachean, away from heroism and towards eros. She
argues that the entire poem is the attempt of a Callimachean
narrator (not identical with Apollonius himself) to subvert the
epic poem of which he is in charge; that the pedantic and
anti-heroic narrator simultaneously subverts the Callimachean
aesthetic of which he is an oversimplified representative and the
Homeric aesthetic to which he is hostile; and that the poem as a
whole is "an epic story changed to an allegory of poetic theory"
(8). For her, the importance of the Euphemus episode is the fact
that Euphemus, via the clod and Thera, is the ancestor of
Callimachus himself. For Jackson, Jason, though not an epic hero
of the old style, is certainly the central figure of the poem,
and the traditionalist heroes (Telamon, Idas, even Heracles) are
discredited; for DeForest, Heracles is--at least to the other
characters in the poem--the main character: "By his failure to
develop into a vital character, Jason does not fill the hole
[left by Heracles], but defines its presence" (69). For her, it
is Medea who is the true hero of the Argonautica.
By now, the divergent perspectives of Jackson and DeForest
have, I hope, become evident: the two of them could comfortably
fit into DeForest's critical allegory of the Argonautica
itself, two characters in the poem disputing the meaning of the
text in which they find themselves. In certain respects, they are
not so far apart in ideas as they are in terminology. Jackson
makes a plea for regarding Jason not as a failed hero but as a
normal human being thrust uncomfortably into a heroic poem (30):
"As a Hellenistic hero Jason is, in fact, not a hero of
non-human proportions at all, but a man, with all man's qualities
and faults. . . . Apollonius' Argonautica is a work of
Hellenistic sensibility composed within the traditional framework
of epic convention, motif and idiom." This is no less acceptable
as a basis of interpretation than is DeForest's more fashionable
metapoetic reading: "Underlying Jason's story is a struggle
between Homeric tradition and Callimachean poetics--a struggle
treated with exquisite irony and humor. The narrator is in
conflict with his poem" (9). The weakness of Jackson's approach
is that he seems almost entirely oblivious to the problems of
Alexandrian poetics; the weakness of DeForest's is that she can
see nothing else.
For DeForest, the opposing perspectives of the poem's
narrator and characters are Callimachean and Homeric
respectively: the Argonauts want to be in a Homeric epic; the
narrator wants to write Callimachean poetry (9). The crew's
choice of Heracles as leader in book 1 is emblematic of the
difference: they, and Jason, are not only different types of
hero, they belong to different genres of poetry. The Callimachean
narrator subverts the epic to which Telamon and the others think
they belong; to do so, he turns it from epic poetry to love, and
then Medea, the protagonist of this Callimachean poem, escapes
her narrator; she deceives and terrifies reader and narrator
alike, destroying epic (allegorically found in the figure of
Talos) as her last act in the poem.
While metapoetics is certainly a legitimate approach to
Alexandrian (or indeed, Roman) poetry, and while the distinction
between author and narrator is an essential one, there are times
at which DeForest's Argonautica seems to have been written
by Pirandello rather than Apollonius. A more serious drawback is
that her imprecise blurring of terms (such as 'heroic' 'epic' and
'Homeric') and her peculiar understanding of Callimachean poetics
seems to me to undermine her whole project. The latter aspect is
quite important, and here DeForest seems aware of her
difficulties and tries hard to muddy the waters. On the one hand,
her narrator is a Callimachean; on the other, he misrepresents
both Homeric and Callimachean poetics through malicious
oversimplification (and to justify this DeForest invokes, briefly
and superficially, Harold Bloom's Anxiety of Influence).
This allows her to eat her cake and have it too: she knows
perfectly well that Callimachus was not a love poet in any
significant sense, but the turn to erotic poetry can be seen by
her parodic-Callimachean narrator as true Callimacheanism; she
can state (in whose voice I am unsure) that "the refusal to write
an epic poem . . . is the central, unifying theme of Callimachus'
poetry" (2), but she is well aware that there is a great deal
more to Callimachus than that. Although she can say that the
significant presence of aetiological tales throughout the
Argonautica is a sign of the narrator's Callimacheanism,
she nowhere recognizes that the very incongruities--of "heroic"
characters in unheroic moments, of peculiar motivations, of the
mixture of the fantastic and the quotidian or the humble and the
grand--that are endemic to all high Alexandrian poetry are an
essential context for the conflict she sees in the
Argonautica between narrator and characters. There is
indeed such a conflict, and DeForest does well to bring it out;
but it is not a metapoetic allegory of the struggle between
Homeric and Callimachean poetics, it is Alexandrianism pure and
simple. Jackson, whose approach to the Argonautica is far
less sophisticated, has managed in this (perhaps through sheer
naivete) to offer a far more sensible reading.
Nor are DeForest's proofs of the Callimacheanism of her
narrator altogether convincing or consistent. She depends on
precise verbal reminiscences of Callimachus to make a number of
her arguments, and yet she knows that the chronological
underpinnings of this approach are shaky at best: her
Argonautica emerges as the final work of high Alexandrian
poetry, completed after 246 (and probably by some years)--
something which I find, if not impossible, highly improbable. She
rests arguments on the repetition of key-words of Callimachean
aesthetics, notably dienekes--but admits that the word
does not have one consistent meaning in Apollonius. Some
arguments are simply wrong: when the Argo passes through the
Symplegades, it is compared to a kulindros, "an ancient
word for the container of book rolls. . . . Just as Athena's hand
pushes the boat, so the reader's hand keeps the story going by
unrolling the volume. . . ." (79) And the argument goes on,
becoming ever more remote from either sense or the text. And it
might be pointed out that the only citation in LSJ for
kulindros in the sense that DeForest wants is from
Diogenes Laertius--scarcely evidence for Alexandrian usage. Add
to this that DeForest's book is filled with irrelevant
digressions, repetitions, and errors, and it will be clear that
the intelligent points that she does have to make about the
narrator of the Argonautica, about Medea, about Jason's
cloak and Orpheus' song, and about other specific passages are
submerged in a welter of misdirection. The Argonautica is
indeed an important part of the Alexandrian debate about the
goals and nature of poetry in the new age, but it is too great a
poem to be pigeonholed as no more than metapoetic allegory.
I ended by being uncertain too about the audience that
DeForest wants to address: there is far too much simple (and
often over-simple) explanation of background for anyone with any
knowledge of Greek literature, but the argument is far too narrow
for anyone but an aficionado of Alexandrian poetry. Ultimately, I
wondered whether this book too has a narrator at odds with its
author and subject.