Thomas, 'Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece', Bryn Mawr Classical Review 9503
URL = http://hegel.lib.ncsu.edu/stacks/serials/bmcr/bmcr-9503-thomas-literacy
@@@@95.3.35, Robb, Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece
Kevin Robb, Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. Pp. 320. $45.00. ISBN
0-19-505905-0.
Reviewed by Carol Thomas -- University of Washington
carolt@u.washington.edu
Just as Albert Lord first assisted, then enlarged the
achievement of Milman Parry, so has Kevin Robb carried the work
associated primarily with Eric Havelock to new levels of
understanding. His Literacy and Paideia in Ancient Greece
reflects the full explication of the thesis trumpeted to an
unreceptive world in Havelock's Preface to Plato (1963);
in fact, it is dedicated to the memory of Eric Alfred Havelock.
Drawing on evidence ranging from understanding of morphological
characteristics of languages to vase paintings and inscriptional
evidence to fundamental institutions of ancient Greek culture,
Robb tracks the insertion of literacy into Greece from the eighth
century into the fourth. Since its use eventually penetrated
every aspect of life, the account offers vivid insights into the
very workings of society during those centuries.
The author's largest premise is that unless something
unforeseen comes to light, "the greatest discovery of the century
in classical scholarship will be the rediscovery of the oral
dimension of Greek life in the Geometric and Archaic periods with
strong residual effects in culture of High Classical and
Classical periods" (253). It is a bold claim, one that will not
staunch debate on the issue. Yet it is a relief, especially to
those of us who found merit in Havelock's original assertions, to
read Robb's thorough, cogent and civil exploration of that
position.
Robb understands the massive barriers still standing against
the view that literacy came late to Greece, that Athenian society
was fully literate in the "institutional" sense only by ca. 350
B.C., a date even later than that argued by Havelock. How could
Greeks forget knowledge of writing possessed during the Mycenaean
Age? How can we explain the Hellenic literacy achievement if we
believe that the Classical Age continued to rely on oral
discourse and a system of education that was itself founded on
oral paideia rather than mastery of written texts? His case
batters such defenses and, at least in the eyes of this reviewer,
renders them useless as defense. One need not dismiss the
literacy accomplishment in order to appreciate the sophisticated
mechanisms of a predominantly oral society. Rather, the two
skills grew together slowly, gradually altering the basic nature
of Classical Greece.
The story unfolds chronologically, beginning with the
origins of Greek literacy in the eighth century, turning then to
the alliance between literacy and the law during the seventh and
sixth centuries, concluding with the alliance between literacy
and paideia established finally about the middle of the fourth
century. An epilogue exploring the invention of the Greek
alphabet in both linguistic and historical terms completes the
book's deftly interwoven argument.
Robb tells the story well, using full notes to treat highly
specialized issues as well as to provide bibliographic
references. His discussion falls into individual sections within
each chapter with a conclusion at the end that urges "let us now
draw the threads together" (61) and points briefly to the next
step of the discussion. By the end, a rich picture emerges,
composed from all the topics. Socrates' indictment, for example,
may plausibly be charged to his undermining of the traditional
institution of sunousia inherent in the oral paideia which
continued in Athens until well into the fourth century. The
nature of the law under which Socrates was tried, by contrast,
can be seen as reflecting a new alliance between law and
literacy.
Especially pleasing is Robb's use of the work of others; he
builds his account by recognizing the past and current
scholarship out of which his own views have grown. In the
process, he acknowledges the well-known accomplishments of
scholars like Milman Parry but also rescues from near oblivion
classicists like Frank Byron Jevons, writing in the 1880s, who is
"known today only to a scattering of the world's classicists and
a handful of scholars associated with his home university" (258).
Every scholar should acknowledge debts but Robb is exceptional in
his graciousness--Henry Immerwahr "putting Greek scholarship in
his debt" (185). Even in criticism, he is kind: showing his debt
to Michael Gagarin, he admits "I am less sure, but possibly
Gagarin is right, as often on these matters he is" (113). On an
even larger scale, Robb manages to avoid hostile debate; in the
epilogue on the origin of the alphabet, the simplification of
writing achieved in the Semitic unvocalized syllabary of the
sixteenth century is credited with preparing the way for the
later Greek invention. I detect nothing vituperative in the
entire book, a greater accomplishment when one remembers how
Havelock's thesis was greeted in reviews!
The range of primary evidence is equally wide and mixed
together. In addition to inscriptional material, Robb looks to
the information to be gained from physical remains themselves
noting, for example, the nature of fabric for dating purposes or
when professional tools were employed for inscribing. The Homeric
corpus is of primary importance to his case; comparative evidence
plays a role; and common sense is ever present. For example, in
arguing against a complete text of the Iliad, Robb asks
how one accounts for the source of the 300 feet of papyrus needed
for a text of the Iliad if trade with Egypt began only in
the seventh century.
Paideia and law are the main thrusts of the study. They are
happily joined in Robb's view of the earliest evidence for
literacy, namely that the motive for adoption of the alphabet was
to record hexameter verse, not as literary text, but in short
inscriptions that probably served votive uses. The earliest
inscriptions demonstrate a widespread absorption of Homeric or
epical verse at the popular level, indicating that the social
motive behind such absorption was the role epical verse played in
oral paideia. While always artful narrative, verse was also
prescriptive, carrying in it the rules of society.
The first new alliance of orality/literacy occurred in
defining these rules. The Gortyn Code is both a key document in
the history of Greek law and a key to understanding advancing
literacy. Robb masterfully treats the two roles of judicial
officials: one procedure existed in cases that were regulated by
written regulation while another was linked to reliance on
ancient, oral custom. The discussion of witnessing,
maturia, as procedural witnessing is compelling. Not so
persuasive is the view that "oral societies...do not really have
'law' as we understand the term" (n. 25, p. 41). "It is very
strange that written laws first addressed matters not felt to be
at the core of communal concern or accepted practice" (87), yet
these core concerns were not as closely regulated by oral
procedure as written provisions were by other means. And the
"missing" binding element is surely non-human enforcement, the
thioi addressed at the onset of the Gortyn Code. I am
altogether ready to admit that after 399 B.C., at least in
Athens, nomos was equated with written law. Earlier,
however, in Athens and elsewhere oral "law" was nomos.
On only one other subject is Robb's contention not fully
convincing. Linking fifth century Athenian progress toward
popular literacy with democracy and written law, Robb states that
written skills were needed by citizens "to fulfill their
political--and especially legal obligations and opportunities"
(125). What literate skills were required for assembly, boule or
heliaia? Do deme lists truly require extensive records at local
levels? And how were such skills to be gained in a polis where,
as Robb argues persuasively, paideia was still primarily oral and
poetic? Even as late as the time that the Republic was
composed, "participation in the communal life of the city....was
the primary mechanism of this oral paideia" (197).
On the other hand, he makes a good case for growing reliance
on literacy as a result of demands of empire and careful
cataloging of laws in the Nichomachian code. Their effect can be
seen in changes in paideia proposed in the Republic and,
following Robb's view, put in place in the Academy. While there
is no provision for teaching of letters in Plato's dialogue,
those very dialogues may well have been "textbooks", putting
students in direct contact with the methods of Socrates (235). As
such they were transitional texts; only in the Lyceum did the
systematic study of texts replace reliance on oral habits (221).
The possible historical evolution of the Academy is skillfully
recreated.
And since the author probes paideia as the nature of life,
the study contains much insightful social history; the Ithacan
wine jug serving as a xenos-gift (51), a father turning to
Homeric speech to compose an epitaph for his son which his
friend, a local stonemason, would inscribe on the grave-marker
(65); the interaction between a friendly Phoenician and a Greek
craftsman in giving birth to the Greek alphabet (272 f.).
Wonderful turns of phrase increase the effectiveness of these
insights: "'Homer' helping nobles get through those long, cold
Geometric nights" (177).
The book does not want for controversial issues, Robb admits
candidly (252). His non-confrontational manner goes a long way in
explaining his success. Literacy and Paideia in Ancient
Greece is a fit tribute to Eric Havelock. It is also the mark
of continued growth in our understanding of the inmost workings
of Classical Greece.