Inwood, 'Prolegomena: Questions to be Settled before the Study of an Author or a Text', Bryn Mawr Classical Review 9503
URL = http://hegel.lib.ncsu.edu/stacks/serials/bmcr/bmcr-9503-inwood-prolegomena
@@@@95.3.25, Mansfeld, Prolegomena
Jaap Mansfeld, Prolegomena: Questions to be Settled before the
Study of an Author or a Text. Leiden: Brill, 1994. Pp.
vii+246. $57.25. ISBN 90-04-10084-9.
Reviewed by Brad Inwood -- University of Toronto
Brill has now reached volume 61 in its series Philosophia
Antiqua with this learned and useful monograph by Jaap
Mansfeld. Mansfeld's work in the field of later Greek philosophy
and the doxographical tradition continues to make important
contributions to our understanding of ancient thought. The
present volume tackles aspects of a difficult preliminary
question which ought in principle to precede any attempt to
comprehend the philosophical texts which survive from antiquity:
why are they in the form they are in, and how were they meant to
be read in their own day. Without some view about the
presuppositions which ancient readers brought to their
philosophical texts, we cannot satisfactorily grasp how and why
their authors wrote them as they did. Some understanding of
literary hermeneutics, in at least this sense, is a necessary
part of any reading of ancient philosophical texts. We are
familiar with the importance of the dialogue form for
interpreting Plato and with the vital role played by modern views
about the nature of Aristotle's 'treatises' in our assessments of
his work. The differences between the letters of Epicurus and his
massive work On Nature affect our understanding of
Epicureanism almost as much as does our appreciation of the
difference between either of those works and Lucretius'
philosophical poem.
Mansfeld's theme is more specific, and certainly less
familiar to most students of antiquity: the ancient tradition of
writing philosophical commentaries, and in particular the
organized prefaces meant to be propaedeutic to the reading of
difficult and important texts. This is, then, in large measure a
study of later ancient philosophical pedagogy, for it is these
late ancient texts which his study helps us to understand, rather
than the earlier texts (Plato, Aristotle, and so forth) on which
they comment. Mansfeld's theme and evidence range very widely
indeed. In assembling his picture of the schema isagogicum
he draws on at least the following blocks of material:
- Proclus' introductions and commentaries on Plato
- Proclus' commentaries on Euclid
- Proclus on Homer and Hesiod
- the anonymous Theaetetus commentator
- various commentaries on Aristotle
- Christian commentaries on scripture
- commentaries on Virgil
- commentaries on Aratus
- rhetorical and medical commentaries
From this fertile field, which he knows intimately, Mansfeld
unearths and brings together an impressive amount of evidence in
favour of the thesis that there eventually developed a more or
less standard introductory scheme for use in schools as a
preparation for the detailed study of texts of almost any genre
with the aid of a specialized commentary. The fullest form of
this scheme is that found in the school of Proclus, and Mansfeld
identifies seven components (10-11):
- the theme of the work under study
- its position in the corpus
- its usefulness
- discussion of the title, if obscure
- authenticity
- its division into sections or chapters
- the branch of philosophy to which it belongs
The argument and exposition in chapter one are exhaustive.
Mansfeld meticulously tracks down anticipations of these themes
in commentary or introductory texts over a wide range of fields
as early as the Hellenistic commentaries on Aratus. It is
probably too much to suppose that a self-conscious tradition or
genre of such writings goes back that far; after all, most of
these questions would force themselves naturally onto almost any
commentator dealing with 'ancient' texts, even without the
benefit of a learnt tradition. (My one complaint about Mansfeld's
technique is that he may be too ready to crystallize ancient
scholarly comments into a schema or genre of commentary,
when all we have is evidence that scattered authors asked similar
questions; note the birth of a 'sub-genre' by p. 181.) But
Mansfeld is surely right to emphasize (following the work of
Neuschaefer and Hadot) the cardinal role of Origen, whose
commentary on the Song of Songs is already structured by a
schema which is a somewhat simpler predecessor of what we
find in Proclus.
In chapter 2 Mansfeld focusses more narrowly on the Platonic
tradition, and in particular on the complex relations between
Diogenes Laertius' Life of Plato and middle Platonic
writers such as Dercyllides and Albinus (author of the
Prologos; Mansfeld follows Whittaker in recognizing that
Alcinous wrote the Didascalicos). Historians of Platonism
will find a great deal to debate here, but the most important
theme is the relationship between the Thrasyllan 'recension' of
Plato's works and Diogenes' account. This entire field has been
the focus of lively debate, and Mansfeld takes account of
contributions as recent as Harold Tarrant's 1993 book
Thrasyllan Platonism. Mansfeld argues that the
ordering by trilogies precedes the tetralogic plan used by
Thrasyllus (though there was also a pre-Thrasyllan tetralogic
order). The principles used by Thrasyllus can, according to
Mansfeld, be partially discerned. Pythagorean numerology plays a
role (if only so that a numerically tidy canon might be more
stable in transmission). The effect of Hellenistic
schematizations of philosophy is evident, but "it would seem that
most of the time Thrasyllus still applies literary rather than
philosophical criteria, just as Aristophanes had done before him"
(70). In the rest of the chapter a very detailed discussion of
the classifications of Platonic dialogues used by middle Platonic
writers brings out the differences between what Mansfeld calls
the "tetralogic canon" (91) stemming from Thrasyllus and the
systematic ordering designed to support a distinctly middle
Platonic teaching programme which developed by the time of
Albinus.
The interconnection of literary and philosophical
considerations also marks chapter 3, a short study of Porphyry's
Vita Plotini as an example of the introductory essay in
the genre under consideration. Comparison is made with Arrian's
treatment of Epictetus' corpus; the frequently studied Vita
Plotini benefits from this perhaps unexpected juxtaposition.
Mansfeld's broad generic approach to philosophical introductions
is justified in this chapter by his successful treatment of
Porphyry's puzzling invocation of the scholar Apollodorus
alongside Andronicus as a model for the systematic rather than
the chronological ordering of texts (V. Plot. 24).
Apollodorus was responsible for the standard edition of the comic
poet Epicharmus, just as Andronicus was for Aristotle and
Theophrastus. Porphyry's sense of his task in writing the
introduction to his edition of the Enneads is clearly
revealed; he treats the philosophical text according to the
canons applicable to all literary corpora.
The chapter on the Vita Plotini makes a small but
important contribution to the understanding of Plotinus' corpus.
Chapters four and five deal at length with Galen: the
autobiographical treatments of his corpus, his practice as a
commentator on Hippocrates, and his practice of textual exegesis.
Galen is portrayed convincingly as working within the exegetical
tradition under study, but not following its conventions too
closely. Mansfeld is here breaking new ground. While a great deal
remains to be done, it is clear that these chapters form an
indispensable starting point for future attempts to grapple with
the exegetical practice of this most prolific of ancient authors.
Historians of ancient medicine will find this an important
discussion, and historians of Stoicism can now develop a better
understanding of Galen's The Doctrines of Plato and
Hippocrates, a crucial text for understanding Stoic ethics.
In his final chapter Mansfeld explores the exegetical
importance of biography. How, and why, should biographical data
about an author be used in understanding his text? The question
is still current, though the ancient assumption that biography
matters crucially is now out of fashion. Mansfeld begins,
somewhat surprisingly, with a short passage from Cicero's De
Inventione (2.117) to which Schaeublin has drawn attention.
Contentious or ambiguous written texts, especially legal
documents, are to be interpreted in the light of the writer's
life and character as well as the rest of his corpus and the full
context of the document under discussion. The relevance of the
whole document is obvious; that we should strive to harmonize our
reading with the whole corpus is rather more surprising to us
(what if the author changed his mind over time?). But it is the
importance of biography to the interpretation of texts which
really stands out. Modern students of ancient literature are more
familiar with the notion that the biographies of ancient writers
are tainted by retrojection of 'facts' both large and small from
the works. Using the biographies to interpret texts would then be
circular.
Mansfeld sets aside such worries (180) and explores the
historical implications of this practice, which he shows to be
widespread in later antiquity. Biography and doxography play
themselves out side by side, interacting in complex ways with
each other and with the formal commentary tradition. Specialists
in ancient philosophy are prone to rather inconsistent uses of
Diogenes' biographical material, neglecting it, accepting it
uncritically, or exploiting it inconsistently. Mansfeld gives us
here an important tool to use in the task of helping us to make
more critical use of Diogenes' evidence.
Prolegomena is a breathtakingly learned book, from
the introduction through to the series of lengthy 'complementary
notes' which examine points of detail too bulky to be
accommodated in the already dense footnotes. The bibliography is
thorough and up-to-date and the Indices Locorum and
Nominum et Rerum are professional and thorough. The wealth
of material may make the argument hard to follow at some points,
and many readers will no doubt flag at the volume of detail. But
the weary traveller should be sustained by the knowledge that
Mansfeld's labours have helped us along a very important road
towards the understanding of the history of ancient philosophy
and scholarship. We are nowhere near the end of that road, but
the way forward will be much clearer after one absorbs what
Mansfeld given us in this splendid book.